Ben Colburn, pictured above (credit to Norman Fraser) was a Research Fellow at Corpus Christi College, Cambridge and Affiliated Lecturer, Faculty of Philosophy, University of Cambridge until September 2010 when he became a lecturer in philosophy at the University of Glasgow. He recently gave a lecture to the Social Liberal Forum (Scotland) on the subject of Social Liberal Values. From Monday to Wednesday, you've seen the main body of the lecture. This is his appendix in which he reports on the questions he took from the floor of the event. Enjoy - and as I'm away on my holidays, play nicely in the comments threads If you missed it, you might want to also read Robert Brown's speech from the same event.
I am really grateful to Ben for letting me publish this in full. I hope it stimulates and informs debate within the party, not just in Scotland, as we seek to develop our policies for 2015 and beyond.
The Questions
The preceding is a slightly revised
version of a talk I gave at the meeting of the Social Liberal Forum (Scotland ) on 23 June 2012 . It
summarises, and incorporates, material from my essay ‘Liberalism for the People
– the Orange Book challenged’, in The Little Yellow Book edited by RobertBrown and Nigel Lindsay, and published by Liberal Futures in March 2012. Those
who want a little more detail on the ideas above should get their hands on a
copy; they will also find, elsewhere in the volume, a set of cracking essays
which explore different theoretical aspects of social Liberalism, and develop
(better than I have) some specific policy proposals on these foundations. Those
who want a lot more detail on these
ideas might want to track down my monograph Autonomy
and Liberalism (New York :
Routledge, 2010), which will hopefully be coming out in paperback soon.
To conclude, I want to reflect on
some of the comments that this talk elicited from the Social Liberal Forum
meeting.
Complex foundations
In response to Elspeth’s
question, I’ve somewhat clarified above what I mean by ‘instrumental value’,
and in particular I’ve distinguished it from ‘conditional value’. (The former
is a relation between two political aims: one aim or value is instrumental when
it is advanced as a way of achieving some
other aim or value. The latter is what we mean when we say that something is
valuable only under certain conditions.) I think I’ve also made it a bit
clearer how the whole theory fits together. At the foundation lies the ideal of
individual autonomy, which means an individual deciding for herself what is
valuable, and successfully living her life in accordance with that decision.
For political purposes, this ideal has two components: social liberty, and
individual responsibility. A political programme based on autonomy must support
and promote both of these as far as possible: they are, we might say, instrumentally but
unconditionally valuable.[1]
And doing that requires that we take
a stance toward to the other forms of liberty: personal, political, and
economic. These often support both social liberty and individual
responsibility, but not always. So, they are instrumentally and conditionally valuable. Their pursuit in
politics must be constrained by a supportive context to ensure that they
enhance, rather than detracting from, individual autonomy. My five key
questions are intended to articulate this constraint in a way which allows us
to audit particular policies to see how far they match up to the fundamental
social Liberal principles set out here.
So far, so good. But I think
there’s a deeper problem raised by Elspeth’s question, which has to do with the
role of complex theory in practical politics.
In one sense, I don’t think we
need to be afraid of complexity. Social and political life is complex; we
should expect that an adequate political theory will mirror that complexity. As
Liberals, we should eschew the tendency we see in other political movements
towards procrusteanism; that is, insisting upon an over-simple theory of
politics, and twisting the evidence and the reality to try to make it fit.
Nevertheless, theoretical complexity
does pose us a practical political problem: how do we articulate these basic
social Liberal principles so that they resonate with voters? As it happens, I
don’t think that the theory I’ve sketched is so complex as to preclude
communication by a talented political commentator. Take the core concepts: the
importance of responsibility; the fact that different people’s liberties, and
different types of liberty, can come into conflict; and the value of someone
shaping their own life according to their judgement about what is valuable that
the ideal of individual autonomy asserts. These concepts, though not always
framed in the terms I’ve used here, are ones which most people grapple with daily.
The problem is that this quotidian political thought has become completely
disconnected, in most people’s eyes, from the political process in Britain . In my
essay in The Little Yellow Book I
suggested that this depressing fact offers us Liberal Democrats an important
opportunity. We are justly proud of our experience in community politics. The
logical next step in that journey is to start talking about political theory,
and connecting with the political thinking that people don’t realise they’re
doing. This will help to rebuild trust and electoral success at the grass
roots. Apart from anything else, it will show that we are ambitious, both for
our Liberal ideas and for the good sense of the British population.
The common good
This is a penetrating question,
and one to which I have no quick answer. All I can really hope to do here is to
set out my current thinking on the matter, but it’s clear that this is a point
which I (and social Liberals more general) need to work out much more carefully
than I have time to right now.
The first thing to say is: the
fact that at its roots my theory rests on an ideal of the good life for
individuals doesn’t make it atomistic or ignorant of the common weal. As I said
above, the Liberal recognises that individuals are of necessity embedded in a
rich network of communal life: families, groups of friends, neighbourhoods
churches, schools, universities, campaigning groups, political parties, and
society more broadly. So, taking individuals seriously just means taking seriously the communal life to which they are
committed. The libertarian view that treating individuals seriously means
thinking that there’s no such thing as society – to allude to a famous
misquotation of Margaret Thatcher – is simply mistaken about human nature: the
atomistic and autarchical individuals which it posits do not, never have, and
never will exist.
Above, in my discussion of
responsibility, I indicate what I think this means. (That section,
incidentally, has been somewhat bumped up in response to the questions I’ve
referred to.) Let me repeat, and elaborate, here. If we think autonomy is
important, then we’re going to take seriously people’s judgements about what
makes their lives go well. Most people do
place great importance on communal life. So, the social Liberal principles
I’ve stated above imply that Liberals should uphold and support communal life
and the common good, because of the importance it has for individuals. In
particular, we should do whatever we can to support and extend citizens’
opportunities to seek value through engaging in public service, and by
wholehearted community action.
There’s also a point here about
responsibility. One of the things it means to
be socially embedded – born into a particular society at a particular time – is
that we necessarily incur responsibilities: responsibilities to our families
and other educators, to the society and state which provides the framework
within which we live our lives. These responsibilities are inescapable, and a
central part of who we are. Above, I said that an important aspect of the ideal
of autonomy is guaranteeing that people are responsible for how their lives go.
In the present context, that means enabling people to recognise, and live up
to, the responsibilities they have to their fellow citizens. Once again, for
the social Liberal, taking individuals seriously means doing the same for the
common good.
Will my interlocutors be happy
with this? Possibly not. (Robert Brown wasn’t, when I talked to him
afterwards.) ‘Why not just add ‘the common good’ in as an independent
foundational value alongside individual autonomy?’ they might say. ‘Doesn’t
this individualistic foundation concede too much to our opponents?’
I disagree, for two reasons. One
problem with the proposal just essayed is that it risks a return to a la carte liberalism; that is (to
repeat myself) something we must avoid if we are to be intellectually and
politically credible. The other is that, while I share the view that the common
good is tremendously important, I am mindful that appeals to it are frequently
used to disguise policies which, on closer inspection, turn out to be deeply
illiberal.
Let me explain why. To start
with, I should reiterate that the individualist foundations I’ve laid out in
this essay do indeed place a concern for the common good at the heart of social
Liberal politics. Everyone has an inescapable responsibility to do their part
in supporting a political system which guarantees for everyone the basic
conditions of autonomy. It’s a sort of quid-pro-quo: we recognise that the
importance of autonomy gives each individual considerable freedom and
sovereignty over her own life, but only as much as is consistent with showing
the same regard for all of her fellow citizens, and guaranteeing them the same
privileges that she herself is claiming.
To insist that there is still
something lacking is therefore to argue that our conception of the common good
must go beyond this impartial concern for every citizen’s chance of living an
autonomous life. That would result, in effect, in hard-wiring into our
political system some specific judgements about what makes people’s lives go
well. In reply to a question by Paul Coleshill I noted that Liberals are in
other contexts rightly scornful of regimes which dictate ideals to their
citizenry. We regard the imposition on an individual of a conception of the
good life (whether that is by a state, by a church, by a family, or by social
opinion) as one of the forms of oppression which Liberal politics is here to
oppose. Treating the common good as something valuable in itself (rather than, as above, deriving it from the need to show
equal regard for everyone’s autonomy), hence worth giving independent weight to
in our political theory, seems to me not essentially different. John Stuart
Mill, when remarking on the problem that a pure democracy doesn’t necessarily
protect minority rights any better than a tyrant does, referred to the ‘tyranny
of the majority’. We might, similarly,
talk here about the ‘tyranny of the common good’, and ask: how far should a
Liberal society compel people to contribute to these communal ends if they
themselves don’t see any value there? Our answer should be: no more than is
absolutely necessary to secure the basic conditions of a good life for
everyone.
I’m not certain of this. It’s
hard to work out where to draw the shifting boundaries of Liberalism, and I
would be delighted to be persuaded that my worries are unfounded. Nevertheless,
I think that I have to stick to my guns. I’ve shown how – using just the
foundational concern for individual autonomy and the derivative commitments to
liberty and responsibility that it implies – one can generate a substantial
political role for the idea of the common good. So, there’s unlikely to be any
policy disagreement here. Someone might still want to complain that I’m still
not giving the common good sufficient centrality. To substantiate that charge,
though, they bear a burden of proof. That is, they must show that hard-wiring such judgements into politics can (the
worries I’ve expressed here notwithstanding) be part of a consistent and rigorous
social Liberalism. I don’t see how it can. Hence, I think the more modest
social Liberalism presented here is our best bet.
[1]
Actually, I should say that they are constitutively valuable rather than
instrumentally valuable, for they are components of the ideal of autonomy, and
not independent means to that end – but the distinction needn’t worry us here.
1 comment:
Thanks for giving the talk, Ben - as as social democrat I sincerely appreciate your detailed summary of the social liberal position. Clarity is a signal virtue in these matters, and I look forward to employing it myself later this year.
Post a Comment